Lecture Notes by Anthony Zhang.

PHIL145

Critical Thinking

Instructor: Michael "Mike" McEwan
Section 001
Email: mmcewan@uwaterloo.ca
Office: Hagey Hall 362
Office hours: Mondays 1:00pm-3:00pm, first come, first serve
TA: Teresa Branch-Smith
Office Hours: Wednesdays 11:30am-1:00pm in HH 362

6/1/14

Midterm Feb. 25 in AL 116 4pm.

All exams are not cumulative, only covering half of the course materiel.

Make sure to read the course outline on LEARN.

This course uses i-Clickers. Register the clickers on the registration page.

When emailing instructors, put "Phil 145" in the subject line.

Lectures supplement the lectures, covers the important parts of the readings.

People with laptops should sit at the back. I should probably bring my glasses in that case.

Lecture slides, announcements, and quizzes are available on LEARN.

General goal of course is to improve reasoning skills - differentiating between good/bad reasoning (evaluative), and communicate reasoning/evalutations of reasoning to others (communicative).

Topics:

Common sense is not as common as it might seem. Ideas are only obvious after we have already been exposed to them. Human beings make systematic and widespread errors in their reasoning that seem perfectly reasonable.

8/1/14

Critical Thinking

Refer to CS135 notes for i-Clicker setup. The frequency code is BA.

What is critical thinking? How do we develop critical thinking skills?

Critical thinking is a type of thinking where one reasons in a reliable or successful way.

Reasoning is a cognitive process of deliberation that results in the formation of belief, a judgement, or a choice. This course focuses on beliefs.

One way to determine whether reasoning is successful or reliable is to consider the properties of the beliefs, judgements, and choices that it results in.

We want the resulting beliefs to be true, or at least probably true, and possibly others, like simplicity, coherence with other beliefs, correspondence with the world, etc.

So we want to reason successfully, and only successful reasoning results in true beliefs. Therefore:

Critical thinking is reasoning in a way that leads to the production of true (or approximately or probably true) beliefs.
Critical thinking is successful or reliable reasoning.

We care about true beliefs because people are more likely to be successful (achieve their goals) if they act on true beliefs.

How do we learn to reason reliably?

There are two types of reasoning:

The metacognitive approach is learning how to think about thinking. Learning to think well about a subject means learning new concepts and how to apply them. Likewise with reasoning. We will use these concepts to analyze, explain, criticize, and correct reasoning.

Critical thinking is a philosophy class for historical reasons, but there are also many connections between the fields. Math, science, psychology, and a lot of other fields are simply branches of philosophy. Philosophical questions often require looking into domain-general reasoning, and has close connections to critical thinking.

10/1/14

Consider Zeno's paradox:

  1. Achilles wants to run from point A to B.
  2. To do this, he must go from the first point to halfway to the second point.
  3. He must also go to halfway again to the second point.
  4. This repeats infinitely.
  5. Therefore, Achilles can never finish the race.

This argument seems reasonable, but the conclusion is clearly false. How is this possible? In fact, all the premises are true, but they do not support the conclusion.

This is because the distance becomes infinitely small, while the amount of time taken is also infinitely small. Mathematically, the sum of the times converges to a finite value even though there are an infinite number of times.

Reasoning

Philosophical questions are often questions with no established methods for solving them. "Is the stove on?" has established methods for solving - check the stove.

Philosophers develop concepts and methods of looking at the reasoning about these questions. Domain-general reasoning is often the only way we can look a these problems when they are too new or difficult to solve otherwise. This is also useful in math, logic, science, etc.

Reasoning is the process of deliberation whereby one draws a conclusion.

One of our metacognitive abilities is the ability to give reasons. When we give reasons, we put the aspects of reasoning on display. Reasons are offered in support of the conclusion - they play a justificatory role.

When we examine reasons, we can evaluate the reliability of the reasoning and how acceptable the conclusions are.

Presenting an argument is a way of giving expression in language to our reasons - a way of putting reasoning on display.

The study of argumentation lets us hone our reasoning skills.

An argument can mean a fight or a disagreement, but also a reasoned defence of a claim. We are more interested in the second definition.

An argument can also be abstracted into a set of premises implying a conclusion.

People can say the same words in the same sentence but communicate different things: "one is a prime number.", "is one a prime number?". How do we differentiate assertions, promises, threats, questions, and other types of sentences? In the previous example, the two imply different relationships between the person (knowing vs. not knowing) and the claim and asks different things of the audience (agreeing vs. answering).

What is the real difference between these different ways of communicate the same words? Everything is said in a certain context, which is an important part of understanding the intent of the words.

Assertions are claims presented as true. By asserting a claim:

13/1/14

Committing to defending assertions has multiple benefits: filtering information, checking our beliefs against others', helping us change our minds, and explaining our reasoning being helpful for clarifying/organizing our own beliefs.

Identifying Arguments

The fundamental unit of rational exchange is the argument. Arguments show the reasonableness of an assertion - if the argument succeeds in doing so, everyone is justified in believing the assertion is true.

Two working definitions of arguments:

The broad definition focuses on the practise of argumentation and connects it to assertion - the communicative act.

The narrow definition focuses on the products of the communicative act. This is what we will focus on in this course.

Most things where the broad definition applies also has the narrow definition apply - the narrow definition is virtually a subset of the broad one.

Arguments are often presented as sets of sentences. We will be studying the narrow definition more in the coming weeks.

When is a set of sentences an argument? There must be a conclusion - an assertion - and premises that defend this assertion. A good argument has premises that the audience already accepts.

Toronto is the largest city in Canada.

This is not an argument, because there is only a conclusion, without any supporting premises.

Will you get lost if you walk around Toronto?

There is neither a conclusion or any premises.

Don't get lost when you walk around Toronto. I will make fun of you forever if you do.

There are two assertions, both conclusions. Neither of the assertions support each other.

You will get lost if you walk around Toronto. It is the largest city in Canada.

This is an argument, though not a very strong one. The premise that the city is large implies the conclusion that it is more likely that one will get lost.

To determine whether something is an argument, all three of the following must be true:

15/1/14

Assertions are the same thing as claims in this course - the terms are interchangeable.

Descartes argues that anyone who thinks, can know they exist. He reasons that a precondition of thinking is existence.

This is just reporting what was said, not an argument.

Note that the second sentence, describing Descartes' reasoning, does not support the claim that anyone who thinks can know they exists. In other words, the second sentence does not support the first, because the second sentence is a report rather than a premise.

Rules of thumb for identifying arguments:

Note that there are exceptions to these rules. For example, for the second point, a rhetorical question can make a claim in English, and so the conclusion can be a question. The context of the statements matters.

Sometimes arguments may be explicitly identified, with "I argue that ", "This is because ", "Therefore, ", "It follows that ".

Look out for conclusions not at the end of passages, implicit premises, implicit conclusions, and rhetorical questions. Rhetorical questions should be treated like claims.

Explanations

An explanation differs from an argument in that the author intends that the conclusion is already believed by others, rather than trying to convince others. Arguments aim to how something is worth believing, while explanations make better sense of what is already believed. It is the intent of the author that is important.

Therefore, whether something is an argument or an explanation depends on whether the author thinks the audience already believes it: "Professional athletes are physically fit because they train every day" is an argument for people who don't believe that they are fit, and otherwise an explanation.

17/1/14

Arguments can be categorized by how the author intends for the premises to support the conclusion.

Overview of argument types:

Deductive arguments aim for soundness. They are non-ampliative and truth-preserving (we can never start with true premises and reach a false conclusion). Deductive arguments have their premises either support the conclusion perfectly, or not at all - they are all-or-nothing.

Sound deductive arguments guarantee the truth of the conclusion. A sound deductive argument is said to entail its conclusion.

An argument is sound if and only if it is valid and all the premises of the argument are true. To evaluate a deductive argument, we need to ensure that these two conditions are met.

An argument is valid if and only if there is no way for the conclusion to be false if the premises are true. If an argument is valid, then the truth of the premises guarantees the truth of the conclusion. Valid arguments do not require us to look at the world - it only looks at the relationship between statements.

A valid argument does not tell us whether the premises are true, and therefore does not tell us if the conclusion is true.

We can prove that an argument is not valid by using the method of counter-example. A counter-example is a possible case where the premises are true, but the conclusion is false. We only need to find one counter-example to disprove validity. If there are no counter-examples, then the argument is proven valid.

Prime numbers are only divisible by 1 and themselves.
All even numbers are divisible by 2.
-----------------------------------------------------
All prime numbers are odd.

Here, a counter-example would be 2, which is prime but even.

We must be sure that the counter-example is possible:

Either you are taller than me or you are shorter than me.
You are not taller than me.
---------------------------------------------------------
You are shorter than me.

Here, the counter-example "You are the same height" is not admissible because this does not satisfy the first premise.

Usually, the content of the argument determines whether it is valid:

Bob is a bachelor
-----------------------
Bob is an unmarried man

In some special cases, the form of the argument itself is enough to determine whether it is valid:

Bob is a bachelor
-----------------
Bob is a bachelor

A common form is modus ponens:

If P, then Q
P
------------
Q

Another is hypothetical syllogism:

If P, then Q
If Q, then R
------------
If P, then R

Here, P and Q represent claims that can be asserted. They can be as complicated as we like.

There are a variety of valid forms. A sample of them is available in the Week 2 lecture slides, slide 50 in particular.

We can combine argument forms to get more complex arguments. For example, hypothetical syllogism and modus ponens together:

If P, then Q
If Q, then R
P
------------
If P, then R ; derived premises
------------
R

This is the basis of mathematical proof theory.

20/1/14

We can tentatively evaluate an argument's validity by matching it against the valid argument forms and trying to think of counter-examples.

If Pi is less than 4, then God exists.
Pi is less than 4.
--------------------------------------
God exists.

This is valid but not rationally compelling. Validity is not enough to determine whether an argument is "good".

Our goal is to obtain true conclusions.

However, arguments can be valid, yet have false conclusions. Additionally, they might not offer relevant support for the conclusion - the first premise in the above argument is unlikely to be accepted by the audience.

Validity is a property of the structure of an argument.

A premise can be supported by other premises. These other premises support a conclusion, which is then treated as a premise in our argument. These sub-arguments appear often in more complex arguments. All the sub-arguments must be valid for an argument to be valid. For example, the combined argument above can be written as:

Linked support is when two or more premises only entail the conclusion together:

The snow is white
The grass is green
----------------------------------------
The snow is white and the grass is green

Convergent support is when one or more premises independently entail the conclusion. Any one of the premises can make the conclusion true:

The snow is white
The grass is green
---------------------------------------
The snow is white or the grass is green

So when there is only one premise, it always offers convergent support.

We can diagram arguments with their sub-arguments as trees in node-arrow diagrams. We often number the statements and then label the nodes with the statement numbers.

Consider the following argument:

It is either sunny or cloudy. If it is raining, then it is definitely not sunny. It is raining. Therefore, it is not sunny. Therefore, it is cloudy. Therefore, it is cloudy or Bob is your uncle.

We can write it as:

This argument is valid because each sub-argument is valid and it itself is valid.

Truth

Truth is a property of sentences, not arguments or sets of statements. When we say an argument is true, this is not a meaningful statement, but we might mean that it is sound or rationally compelling.

Truth conditions are the conditions under which a sentence is true.

To assert a sentence means to claim it is true. We don't always know for sure if it is true or false.

However, we can judge whether we have good reason to believe the sentence is true or false. We therefore judge the whether it is reasonable to believe whether a deductive argument is sound.

Contingent truths are truths that happen to be true but could have been false if history went a different way. For example, "Waterloo has two universities" could have been false if history unfolded such that one of the universities did not start. Another might be "The Eiffel Tower is in France".

Necessary truths are truths that are true no matter which way history goes, or how the world developed. For example, "All bachelors are unmarried"

Similarly, contingent falsehoods (Waterloo has three universities) and necessary falsehoods (All bachelors are married) exist.

Necessary truths/falsehoods could be that way because of the form, or the content:

"All bachelors are unmarried" is a necessary truth because of the meaning of the word "bachelor", which is part of the content of the sentence.

"If it is raining, then it is raining" is a necessary truth because of the form of the argument itself, and does not require us to know what rain is.

This sentence is false.

The above is neither necessarily true or necessarily false. It is known as the Liar's sentence. People have disagreed on the truth value of this sentence for a long time.

22/1/14

The moon is made of cheese. Therefore, if God exists, then God exists.

The moon is made of cheese
------------------------------
If God exists, then God exists

This is a valid but unsound argument. This is because the truth of the premises always implies the truth of the conclusion - the conclusion is always true, so if the premises are true, then the conclusion is also true.

Compound or complex sentences can be constructed out of atomic sentences. The truth value of these sentences are often determined by the truth value of their component atomic sentences, as well as the logical connectives between the atomic sentences.

An atomic sentence may be something like "It is raining" or "The sky is blue".

Conjunctive

A complex sentence might be "It is raining, but it is warm".

This is a conjunctive sentence - one made up of sub-sentences known as conjuncts, often appearing in the form of "P and/but/however/although/moreover Q".

The conjunctive statement works like a logical AND.

Disjunctive

A complex sentence might be "It is raining, or it is warm" (inclusive or).

This is a disjunctive sentence - one made up of sub-sentences known as disjuncts, often appearing in the form of "P or/unless Q"

The disjunctive statement works like a logical OR.

Sometimes, English implicitly specifies that disjunction is restricted: "You will pass the exam or fail it" implies that you cannot do both. Standard disjunction is an inclusive or, but the special restricted disjunction is an exclusive or. The restricted disjunctive statement is of the form "P or Q (but not both)", or "either P or Q".

If the type of disjunction is not specified, it is open for interpretation, but should be clarified.

Conditional

A complex sentence like "if it is warm, then it is raining" is a conditional sentence. The condition is called the antecedent, and the result is called the consequent.

There are also multiple types of conditionals. The material conditional is always true unless the antecedent is true yet the conclusion is false.

They often take the form of "Q if P", "P only if Q", or "if P, then Q" - these are all equivalent.

It is still true when the antecedent is false because it cannot be invalidated that way.

There is also the subjunctive conditionals: "If Germany had won World War II, then the world would be no different today". This expresses a hypothetical claim - something that would be true if something else is true. The difference is that we already know the antecedent is false, but states what might happen if it were true. These are often distinguished by their using past tense.

A complex sentence like "it is not raining" is a negated sentence - one where a sentence is flipped around to give its opposite. The negated sentence works like a logical NOT, with the form "not P".

24/1/14

Two statements are logically equivalent if they are both true under the same conditions, and false under the same conditions. We represent this relation with P \equiv Q or P \iff Q (P if and only if Q).

We can draw a truth table to do this, and I'm not going to because we already covered this in MATH135.

Ampliative Arguments

An argument is ampliative if the conclusion expresses more information than that expressed in the premises. All valid deductive arguments are by definition non-ampliative, since if they had more information, we could not know that it is valid. As a result, all ampliative arguments cannot be known to be valid.

A non-ampliative argument might be "7 is a prime number, and therefore is only divisible by 1 and 7", while an ampliative one might be "the sun set every day before yesterday, so it will set today".

Ampliative arguments are evaluated based on how well it supports the conclusion. If the premises make the argument rationally believable, then the argument is good. Otherwise, it is not.

We call these arguments cogent. In other words, a cogent argument is one that makes the conclusion rationally believable - it gives us good reaon to believe the conclusion. All sound arguments are by definition cogent.

However, many valid arguments are not cogent, and many invalid arguments are cogent. They are not the same thing.

Cogency is concerned only with the likeliness/probability of counterexamples existing. Cogent arguments have highly unlikely counterexamples or none at all, while Non-cogent arguments have likely counterexamples. In contrast, validity is concerned with the possibility of there being counterexamples at all.

27/1/14

An argument is cogent if the conclusion is more likely than all of its other counterexamples.

The thing about deductive arguments is that since they add no information, we need to start with some information in order to have a deductive argument. Most empirical reasoning (reasoning based on experience or observation) is ampliative. This includes most scientific inferences.

Ampliative arguments have two important properties:

Ampliative arguments can be strengthened or weakened by adding more premises. Cogency is a measure of how well the premises of an ampliative argument supports the conclusion. A strongly cogent argument offers a lot of support, while a weakly cogent argument offers little support.

For example, consider the following ampliative argument:

The entity looks like a duck.
The entity quacks like a duck.
------------------------------
The entity is a duck.

We can weaken an argument by adding information:

The entity looks like a duck.
The entity quacks like a duck.
The entity is swearing loudly in German.
----------------------------------------
The entity is a duck.

Or we can strengthen it:

The entity looks like a duck.
The entity quacks like a duck.
The DNA test indicated duck DNA.
--------------------------------
The entity is a duck.

States of Information

When evaluating a claim, one's state of information is the set of all relevant information/evidence available. Reasoning that is defeasible is always dependent on one's state of information.

The premises in an ampliative argument represent the author's state of information. The audience might have a different state of information, so the cogency of an argument can differ from person to person.

When one has no information or information that points to the conclusion being equally likely to be true or false, one is in a neutral state of information.

In a neutral state of information, it is reasonable to withhold judgement, where we do not accept the proposition, and do not reject it. We simply do not say anything about the truth of the information, since we won't have any information either way.

For example, we are in a neutral state of information with regards to the proposition "the next coin flip will result in heads", because there is no evidence that it is any more likely than tails.

29/1/14

Inductive Arguments

Inductive arguments have conclusions that are unknown cases derived from known cases - "more of the same". For example:

The sun rose yesterday.
The sun rose 2 days ago.
...
The sun rose 394857 days ago.
---------------------------------
The sun will rise again tomorrow.

This is a pretty good inductive argument. Alternatively:

This rose is red.
------------------
All roses are red.

This is not so good an inductive argument.

The premises of an inductive argument used to infer the conclusion are called the inductive base.

How do we evaluate inductive arguments? The strength of inductive arguments is based on how similar the observed and unobserved cases are - how similar the cases in the premises are to the conclusion, in addition to the actual number of observed cases.

In other words, an inductive argument is strong/cogent if and only if it has a large sample size and the samples are representative of the case in the conclusion.

Inductive strength is a matter of degree. Inductive strength is changed if and only if there is new evidence introduced.

Arguments can incorporate all different types of arguments as sub-arguments - for example, an argument might use induction and then modus ponens.

This duck quacked.
Another duck quacked.
All ducks quack.
If it quacks, it is annoying.
-----------------------------
All ducks are annoying.

This is a valid argument - assuming the premises are true, the conclusion will always be true. The inductive part simply makes the argument more cogent, since it provides better reason to believe the premise "All ducks quack".

Abductive Arguments

Abductive arguments have conclusions that unify, explain, or rationalize a set of facts. It is an explanation for the truth of the premises.

They are inferences to the best way to make sense of the observations in the premises.

Ted was standing over the body.
Ted was holding a weapon.
Ted confessed to the crime.
-------------------------------
Ted is the murderer.

This is a strong/cogent abductive argument, because the conclusion explains the premises very well.

I rolled the die twice.
I got 6 both times.
-----------------------
The die is rigged.

Even though the premises are true, the argument is rather weak, because the premises are not really worthy or needing of explanation.

The strength of abductive arguments depends on the ability of the conclusion to explain why the premises are true.

If a premise doesn't really need an explanation, it doesn't really add much support to the conclusion.

As always, we can evaluate cogency/strength by considering how likely the counter-examples are true.

Analogical Arguments

Analogical arguments draw conclusions based on a comparison. There are three important parts:

For example:

The A is similar to B.
The A has property Z.
------------------------------
The B has property Z.

The claims of similarity is often implicit and unstated in the text.

Consider the following analogical argument: "when I visited this doctor he was attentive and sympathetic. I did what he suggested and it solved my problem. If you go see him, he will solve your problem too."

The doctor solved my problem.
You have the same problem as I did.
-----------------------------------
The doctor will solve your problem.

Here, the primary subject is the problem of the person being addressed ("your problem"). The analogue is the author's problem ("my problem"). The claim of similarity is that both problems are the same and that the doctor will treat it the same.

There are also a few types of analogical arguments:

Consider the analogy "the model lost stability in the wind tunnel. Since the model was built to scale, the plane will also lose stability":

The model lost stability.
The model has a similar structure to the plane.
-----------------------------------------------
The plane will lose stability.

This is an inductive analogy, since it draws conclusions about an unobserved case.

Consider the analogy "Society does not shun those suffering from polio or tuberculosis. Why does it shun those with mental health issues?":

Society does not shun those with physical diseases.
Mental and physical diseases are both diseases.
---------------------------------------------------
Society should not shun those with mental diseases.

Consider the analogy "saying you shouldn't take medicine because it's unnatural is like saying we shouldn't ride bicycles because they are unnatural creations":

It is ridiculous to say that we shouldn't ride bicycles because they are unnatural.
Both bicycles and medicine are unnatural.
-----------------------------------------------------------------------------------
It is ridiculous to say that we shouldn't take medicine because it is unnatural.

This is a refutation by analogy, because the consequences in a similar case mean that we cannot accept a claim.

The strength of an analogy is based on the similarities between the analogue and primary subject. More similarity means more cogency and a stronger argument.

We can extend the method of counterexample to analogies. When evaluating analogical arguments, we look for disanalogies - relevant dissimilarities between the primary subject and analogue that weaken the claim to similarity.

Disanalogies simply add premises to an analogical argument that reduce its cogency.

Systematic Argument Evaluation

We now develop a systematic approach to argument evaluation. When evaluating an argument, we can do so using the following process:

  1. Rewrite the argument in standard form.
  2. Diagram the argument structure as a tree or diagram.
  3. Evaluate the argument based on:

We use these criteria to evaluate the validity, soundness, or cogency of any given argument.

Standard Form

Standard form is a way of representing an argument that makes the structure of an argument explicit, making it easy to see the actual argument being made.

In standard form, we put our premises in a numbered list. Implicit premises have their number underlined.

The conclusion goes after the list, separated by a horizontal line (Fitch bar).

When we convert arguments into standard form, we need to first process the premises and conclusion:

Consider the following argument:

Is littering harmful? You bet it is. After all, animals choke on plastic wrappers and people cut themselves on broken glass. I can't stand people that litter! Our elected officials should pass laws against littering because it is their duty to reduce harm whenever possible.

We now identify the conclusion and obvious premises (by looking for keywords like "because" and "after all"), and write each sentence alone, making sure each sentence is fully formed and stands alone:

1. Is littering harmful?
2. You bet [littering] is [harmful].
3. After all, animals choke on plastic wrappers and people cut themselves on broken glass.
4. I can't stand people that litter!
5. It is [our elected officials'] duty to reduce harm whenever possible.
------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------
6. Our elected officials should pass laws against littering.

Now we remove all sentences that are not premises or the conclusion, and all extraneous words to make every sentence an assertion with its own truth value:

1. [Littering] is [harmful].
2. Animals choke on plastic wrappers and people cut themselves on broken glass.
3. It is [our elected officials'] duty to reduce harm whenever possible.
-------------------------------------------------------------------------------
4. Our elected officials should pass laws against littering.

Now we insert implicit premises as needed:

1. [Littering] is [harmful].
2. Animals choke on plastic wrappers and people cut themselves on broken glass.
3. It is [our elected officials'] duty to reduce harm whenever possible.
<u>4</u>. Passing laws against something helps reduce it.
-------------------------------------------------------------------------------
5. Our elected officials should pass laws against littering.

Diagramming

We can now diagram an argument in standard form by drawing a tree-like structure that represents how the premises support the conclusion, including sub-arguments.

This requires distinguishing between the argument conclusion and the conclusions of the sub-arguments.

Each assertion is a node in the tree, labelled with its number, and we draw an arrow from assertion A to assertion B to represent that A supports B.

We represent convergent support with an arrow from each supporting premise:

A B
| |
---
 |
 v
 C

We represent linked support with a + and use only a single arrow from it:

A + B
  |
  v
  C

For example, the example argument above can be diagrammed as follows:

2
|
v
1 + 3 + 4
    |
    v
    5

Evaluation

We first evaluate the acceptability of the premises:

We then evaluate the relevancy of the premises:

Finally, the groundedness:

After doing this, we can say whether the argument is good or bad based on the results of the evaluation.

Note that not every premise of the argument needs to be acceptable, relevant, and grounded in order for the argument to be cogent. In some arguments, certain premises can be discarded without the argument losing its cogency.

In contrast, certain premises are critical premises. These are the premises that are very important to the argument being cogent. If critical premises are removed, the argument is no longer cogent.

When evaluating arguments, we often want to analyze the critical premises first, since if we find any issues here, we can say right away that the argument isn't good.

This is often those premises comprising linked support, or convergent support that is the only support for something.

A cogent argument only requires that there is enough acceptable and relevant premises to ground the conclusion.

In our example above, the premises are all relevant to the conclusion (2 is positively relevant to 1, and 1+3+4 is positively relevant to 5), and the argument and all sub-arguments are all well grounded (accepting 2 makes it reasonable to accept 1, and accepting 1, 3, and 4 makes it reasonable to accept 5).

However, assertion 3, that elected officials are to reduce harm, is not very acceptable. Therefore, the argument is not very cogent.

3/2/14

Mostly review from last class.

Acceptability

There is not always a single interpretation of an argument that is considered correct. This is especially obvious when dealing with the acceptability condition - everyone holds their own set of beliefs that influences what premises they will find acceptable.

Many contingent truths are widely believed. If we do not have any reason not to believe it, then it is reasonable to accept them when they appear in premises. This is often called "common knowledge". For example, "all humans have hearts", though there may be counterexamples.

However, not all humans have hearts. The claim can be made more acceptable by changing it to "virtually every living human has a heart".

However, they are still defeasible and could possibly be false. For example, "whales are fish" - whales are actually mammals.

Note that even if premises are rejected, the argument can still be cogent. For example, two premises can offer convergent support for the conclusion, and if one premise is rejected, the other still offers support.

Testimony

Many of our beliefs come from testimony - we believe a lot of things that we know only because other people say are true. For example, the information we learned from our parents and teachers.

It is reasonable to accept all testimony as long as we don't have any good reasons to doubt the testifier.

We often doubt the testifier when:

When giving testimony, the trade-off is that the testimony gains acceptance, in return for taking on the obligations of making an assertion.

Appealing to authority is a special case of testimony. A legitimate authority is an entity with special knowledge in a certain domain - experts, research institutions, etc.

The same rules for testimony apply for appeals to authority. However, faulty appeals to authority are most often due to the last point - claims should not exceed the expertise of the authority. For example, claims about the weather from a climate prediction institution should be accepted, but macroeconomic analyses from that institution should not.

However, this applies only to testimony given alone - without any additional justification. The acceptability of testimony without any other support is based on how much we should trust what someone says on their word alone. So even if a non-expert gives a claim, it can still be acceptable if compelling reasons are given.

5/1/14

If two authorities have conflicting views, it is generally reasonable to accept the claims of the more authoritative one. If they are very similar in authority, then it is reasonable to withhold judgement.

Authority can be determined by the amount of experts who agree, and how credible these experts are.

Vageness/Ambiguity

We sometimes reject premises because they are vague or ambiguous. In common use this generally means imprecise, but we want a more precise definition.

Imprecise means that the claim is literally true in a very wide range of cases. For example, "the object is bigger than a breadbox, but smaller than a mountain" - a lot of objects satisfy this.

Imprecision often results from imprecise quantifiers like "many", "few", "some", etc.

Many claims are more imprecise than they could be. However, imprecision is a useful tool in everyday communication.

Imprecision by definition makes a premise more acceptable, because it is true in a larger number of cases. It is not a reason to reject a premise.

However, imprecision has a negative impact on groundedness, since an imprecise statement cannot make as many claims reasonably believable.

A vague/ambiguous claim is one where it is difficult to determine if it is true or false. Since we only accept a premise if it is reasonable to believe it is true, there are certain situations where vague/ambiguous claims cannot be accepted.

A vague claim is one that uses vague terms - terms that have penumbral cases, where we don't know whether they apply or not. The vagueness of a term is determined from how many penumbral cases there are. The vagueness of a claim depends on the quantity and vagueness of the terms it contains.

For example, "This man is balding" is vague, because there are many possible cases where we can't be sure whether the man is balding or not - does losing 1 hair count as balding? Does losing 1000?

A famous example is the Sorites paradox:

1 grain of sand is not a heap.
Adding 1 grain of sand to a heap will not turn a non-heap into a heap.
----------------------------------------------------------------------
1000000 grains of sand are not a heap.

The argument is paradoxical because "heap" is a vague term. We do not know whether heap-ness applies in the penumbral cases, when the sand grains could either form a heap or not form a heap.

There is still disagreement about how to evaluate this. Some people say that there is a certain number of grains that distinguish a heap from a non-heap, but we cannot know it exactly. The problem is caused by the concept of a heap being a vague concept.

An ambiguous claim is one where there are multiple possible meanings of the claim without context to find the correct one. Multiple meanings happen quite often in language, but these are often resolved through context. A claim is ambiguous when the context does not allow us to determine which meaning is correct.

The two types are ambiguity are syntactic (sentence structure can be read in more than one way) and lexical (phrases in sentence have multiple meanings by definition).

For example, "Peter saw a man taking his bike" is syntactically ambiguous because the man could either be taking the man's own bike, or Peter's bike.

For example, "She threw a rock at the bank" is lexically ambiguous because it could be a financial bank, or a river bank.

For example, "There is something somewhere" is not ambiguous, just imprecise. There is only one meaning to this statement.

Consistency

Consistency/inconsistency applies to sets of sentences.

A set of sentences is consistent if it possible for all of them to be true at the same time. For example, "the sky is blue", "the grass is green"

Otherwise, the set is inconsistent. For example, "the sky is blue", "the sky is not blue". This often occurs when two sentences are contradictory or there is a necessary falsehood.

An inconsistent set of sentences is not acceptable as premises in an argument, because at least one sentence in the set is always false.

Necessary falsehoods are a special case of inconsistent sets, where there is only one element in the set.

Basically, a set of sentences is inconsistent if all the sentences together are necessarily false, and consistent otherwise.

7/2/14

Premises

Premises can often have faulty assumptions. These assumptions are not acceptable, so we cannot accept the premise:

The murder weapon was a knife but it hasn't been found yet.

This assumes that there was a murder, and that the murder was done using a knife.

Controversial premises are those that are no more acceptable than the conclusion is. If this is the case, the premises cannot help convince someone that the conclusion is true, since they do not support the conclusion.

One special case of this is begging the question or circular arguments:

The Bible is the true word of God.
The Bible says that humans exist if and only if God exists.
Humans exist.
-----------------------------------------------------------
God exists.

This is a circular argument because the first premise relies on the premise being true. Only someone who already believes the conclusion will accept the premise.

A premise is often acceptable when:

But not when it is vague/ambiguous, inconsistent, uses unacceptable assumptions, or controversial.

These are only guidelines for accepting or rejecting premises, and there are exceptions to many of them. If we are in a neutral state of information about whether to accept or reject a premise, we simply don't consider it when evaluating the argument.

Grounding

Evaluations of grounding are applied to all the premises together as a group.

There are a lot of common errors in reasoning. We call these errors logical fallacies. Some of these include affirming the consequent, denying the antecedent, and equivocation.

Equivocation is when an ambiguous phrase is used in more than one way in the same argument. For example:

Bats are rodents.
Bats are used in baseball.
-----------------------------
Rodents are used in baseball.

The ambiguity here is the dual meaning of the word "bat".

Criticism

Effective criticism of arguments focuses on the most important deficiencies of the argument.

The basic process is analyzing the acceptability, relevancy, and groundedness conditions starting with the most critical premises. This way, we can identify the most important issues with the argument.

Argument criticism has to balance charity and accuracy - we want to attack the strongest possible version of the argument to refute all forms of the argument, but we don't want to go too far to fix the argument and misrepresent it as arguing something it is not.

Evaluate the argument "The US was successful at building democracies in Germany and Japan. Afghanistan has fewer people than Germany and Japan. So, US efforts toward democracy in Afghanistan will be successful.".

First, we write it in standard form:

1. The US was successful at building democracies in Germany and Japan.
2. Afghanistan has fewer people than Germany and Japan.
----------------------------------------------------------------------
3. US efforts toward democracy in Afghanistan will be successful.

Now we can diagram it:

1   2
 \ /
  3

The premises offer convergent support because each one individually supports the conclusion, and the support is not really improved by considering them together.

And finally, evaluation:

Therefore, we conclude that the argument is weakly cogent, and is weakened due to the groundedness condition.

10/2/14

Fallacies

A fallacy is a common mistake in arguments. We learn them in order to be able to detect them more easily and identify/communicate them to other people.

A logical fallacy is a fallacy having to do with the logical form itself.

The study of persuasion is rhetoric. Since the study of arguments is the study of rational persuasion, it is a subfield of rhetoric.

However, by "rhetoric" we often mean those fields of persuasion that are not rational. For example, persuasion by force, bribery, etc.

Rhetorical effects can make poor arguments more persuasive than they should be. This can be the result of:

Grounding

Some fallacies associated with groundedness are:

Conspiracy theories are not themselves fallacies, but the support given for their existing is fallacious.

Conspiracy theories often use arguments from ignorance (lack of support for theory is actually used to support theory) and contrary evidence is used to support the theory (e.g., the cover-up was disproved, so there must be a deeper cover-up in place).

Relevance

There are two types of fallacies associated with relevance: distractors and genetic fallacies.

Distractors are irrelevant topics designed to distract the audience. They add rhetorical force because they draw attention away from deficiencies in the argument and makes the argument look more cogent by adding irrelevant but acceptable premises.

12/2/14

Acceptability

The fallacies associated with acceptability center on errors in the premises.

24/2/14

Review of concepts for exam tomorrow, plus an in-class bonus quiz.

26/2/14

We now focus on reasoning in general, from arguments.

The reason we focused on argumentation is to be able to express our reasoning and evaluate how good our reasoning is.

Representation

Representation is used very often in reasoning, and is usually the first step.

Representation-based Reasoning

We first need to encode a system in the world (the target system) as another form before we can manipulate it. This new form is called the representation. For example, we might represent the dimensions and mass of an object as numbers.

Then we can manipulate the representation. For example, we can multiply numbers together, find the density of the object as a number, and discover that it is less than the density of water.

Finally, we can decode the representation to draw conclusions about the target system - like drawing the conclusion that the object floats in water.

So the process of reasoning by representation includes all three of these steps.

This could have some problems in practice:

Another example is for airplane design. The scale model planes are the representation of the full size plane, and we can test it in a wind tunnel to manipulate the representation. Then, we can use this to draw conclusions about what the scale plane represents - the real airplane.

Simplification

Real world systems are often very complex. Representations tend to leave out everything except the most important details to make it simpler to manipulate.

We need to be aware of what the representation encodes and what it doesn't encode about our target system.

For example, the scale model airplane is meant to represent the shape and aerodynamic properties of the real plane, but not the mass or full sized material properties.

As a result, based on the information encoded, we must constrain our manipulations of the representation to ensure that the result still represents the result in the real thing.

Numbers

Numbers are the most common representations used for values.

We use numbers to represent quantities, ratios, changes, magnitudes, orderings, etc.

For example, distances are not numbers - they are just distances, their own thing. However, they are correlated to numbers. We can then convert between distances and numbers interchangably.

Alternatively, we could represent distances with the amount of time it takes to travel that distance for something moving at some speed, or even represent distances using the alphabet.

Numbers have many similarities have a lot of relevant similarities to distances: they can be added together, they can be ordered, and dividing one into parts has each part also be a number or distance.

As a result, we can use things like distributivity (A(B + C) = AB + AC) over numbers and represent multiple sums of distances, and use A > B over numbers to represent one distance being longer than another.

Consider the example of using numbers to represent hockey tournament rankings. In this case, the numbers obey distributivity, but the rankings do not - a hockey team can lose games yet still be first place. Therefore, the lowest number is not necessarily the best team. In this case, we manipulated the

Ordinal numbers are natural numbers, used to represent positions/rankings. They are used for ordering things.

Cardinal numbers are natural numbers, used to represent size. They are used for counting things without fractional values.

Nominal numbers are numbers that are only used as a name, like postal codes or phone numbers.

Percentages and Operations

Percentages are useful for representing and comparing ratios. This allows us to see which ratio is higher or lower.

Using percentages results in a loss of information. When we use a percentange, we lose all information about what the original numbers were - 25% could represent 10/40 or 1/4. We must make sure to be aware of the numerator and denominator.

If the number of bear attacks increased 100% this decade, should we implement a bear patrol?

It could be that there was 1 attack last decade increasing to 2, or that there were 100 increasing to 200, or a lot of other answers.
If there was only 1 more attack, we could not justify implementing a bear patrol due to resource constraints.
If there were 100 more attacks, we should implement a bear patrol to stop them.
We do not have enough information to answer the question using only percentages.

We must be sure to manipulate numbers only when those manipulations are valid and make sense as well in the target system. For example, adding percentages to get total percentages is an invalid manipulation, as well as taking the inverse sine of a distance, or adding mass to length.

Unit systems help us avoid these situations by making it obvious when we try to add different types of physical quantities. This is useful but not completely effective - it is still possible to go wrong even when using units.

If we add 5 meters and 5 meters, we can straighforwardly say that it represents 10 meters. But if we add 5 meters and 5 kilograms, what does the 10 represent?

A percentage can represent a multiple, or a change. A 50% increase is different from something being 50% of what it was before.

A percentage increase is denoted by \text{Percentage Increase} = \frac{(\text{Later} - \text{Earlier})}{\text{Earlier}} \times 100\%.

Rankings

Numbers are also often used for ranking things due to their ability to be compared - numbers are ordered.

Rankings encode only information about order. For example, the rankings for runners in a race does not encode what the actual times were, or how close the winners were to each other, only information about who was first, second, third, and more.

Rankings are given based on some system of measurement, and the properties of this system determine what the ranking means.

Metrics

In many cases, the measurement system only measures something indirectly, like how IQ tests measure the ability to answer certain questions as a metric for intelligence in general.

Pseudo-precision is when the number is represented in a form that makes it seem like it has more precision than it does. For example, one might claim that pi is approximately equal to 4.03. This number only has 1 significant digit, but it is presented like it has 3.

Average

An average is a number that is supposed to represent a whole set of data. As a result, a lot of information is inevitably lost when using only the average.

The most common ways of finding averages are the mean (ratio of total value to number of values), median (central value when sorted), and mode (most common value).

3/3/14

Statistics

Statistics is the study of data collection and analysis. It is related to critical thinking because it helps determine what kind of techniques, inferences, and interpretations can be used on data sets, and because statistics is used very often in reasoning.

Variables are a type of property. A statistic is a feature of a data set.

A data set is a collection of information, often relating to a population of interest.

The properties of the popoulation are represented using variables. For example a poll of a city might result in a variable being the approval of the current prime minister, and the value of this variable is the percentage of people who do approve.

Often, it isn't possible to measure the whole population. As a result, we choose a smaller sample set that represents the target data set. We always want the sample set to represent the target set as accurately as possible.

We often make inteferences from data sets using inductive generalizations - inferring features of the target data set from the sample data set. We use this to generate hypotheses about the data.

How well a sample represents the population depends in the size of the sample relative to the population, and the randomness of the selection process. Ideally, the selection process would give each individual an equal chance of being considered in the sample. For example, polling by phone selects only those people who own phones, answer them, and have a listed number.

A non-random sample set is biased and might not accurately represent the target population. However, even if we choose our sample randomly, we may still get unlucky and randomly choose a bad sample, which doesn't represent the target population.

From these data sets, we can figure out correlations between variables, which can help us figure out casual relationships.

For example, a political poll has a population of every eligible voter, a sample set of the people who actually voted, and the inference is that the people who voted are an accurate sample of the people who can vote.

Correlation/Causation

A correlation is when variables are related in some way - they co-vary together. Correlations are useful because we can use them to make predictions about what will happen when a variable is a certain way.

For example, if attending class is correlated with high grades, then given students that attend class, we can predict that they have higher grades than those who do not attend class.

Positive correlation is when, given variables x and y, an increase in x results in an increase in y, and vice versa. For example, there is a positive correlation in street signs between signs saying "STOP" and signs that are red.

Negative correlation is when, given variables x and y, an increase in x results in a decrease in y, and vice versa. For example, there is a negative correlation in street signs between signs saying "STOP" and signs that are yellow.

Causation is when one thing causes another thing. Where correlation can be used to make predictions in some circumstances, causation allows predictions to be made in a much larger set of circumstances, and even predict what will happen when we modify other variables.

For example, knowing there is a correlation between smoking and lung cancer is good for predicting whether someone will have lung cancer or a smoking habit, but not for preventing lung cancer. Knowing that smoking causes lung cancer allows us to prevent lung cancer by predicting that stopping smoking helps reduce the incidences of lung cancer.

In other words, knowing smoking is correlated to lung cancer doesn't tell us that changing smoking will change lung cancer.

Null Hyposthesis

When we find a correlation in a sample set, we cann't directly apply it to the target population. The idea that a correlation exists in the target population is a hypothesis.

There could be multiple hypotheses, like that there is a causal relationship between the two variables, or similar.

All hypotheses must compete with the null hypothesis. The null hypothesis is that what we observed was just a fluke or an accident. It is the "baseline" hypothesis, so to speak.

Correlation in sample Correlation in population Result
No, don't reject null hypothesis No, we were right Correct inference
No, don't reject null hypothesis Yes, we were wrong Type II error (false negative)
Yes, reject null hypothesis No, we were wrong Type I error (false positive)
Yes, reject null hypothesis Yes, we were right Correct inference

Note that not rejecting the null hypothesis isn't the same thing as accepting it.

Suppose that several times while riding a bike up a hill, the bicycle chain derails. We can then produce some hypotheses:

Confounds are alternative explanations for observations. Confounds are counterexamples to abductive arguments, and can be thought of as alternative hypotheses:

We must also intriduce the null hypothesis:

Testing Hypotheses

  1. Collect data from a sample to draw hypotheses from.
  2. Reject unrepresentative samples and clean up data.
  3. Figure out correlations in the sample.
  4. Introduce null hypothesis.
  5. Introduce hypotheses about correlation in the population.
  6. Introduce confounds.
  7. Introduce hypotheses about causation in the population that explain the correlations.

5/3/14

Probability

Probability is closely connected to statistics. A probability is a likeliness - the chance of something happening or something being true or similar.

The most common meaning of probability is the relative frequency of something (how often something will happen in the long run, like flipping a coin lands on heads half the time) and degrees of belief (how rationally certain about an event occuring, where 1 is certain and 0 is impossible).

Humans are good at finding patterns, but are prone to false positives - type I errors. Humans are prone to thinking certain things are improbable when they are simply the result of random chance - they are bad at evaluating the null hypothesis.

Formal Treatment

P(x) represents the probability of event x occurring. It is always the case that P(x) \in \mathbb{R} and 0 \le P(x) \le 1 - nothing is more impossible than impossiblity, or more certain than certainty.

\neg x is the opposite of the event x - the event of x not occurring. P(\neg x) is the probability of event x not occuring.

P(S), where S is a set of events, represents the probability of one of those events occurring. If S includes all possible events, then P(S) = 1.

Usually, P(x) = \frac{\text{Number of cases where } x \text{ occurs}}{\text{Total number of cases}}, assuming that all cases are equally likely.

P(x \cup y) is a disjoint probability - the probabilty that at least one of x or y occur.

P(x \cap y) is a conjoint probability - the probabilty that both x and y occur.

P(x \mid y) is a conditional proability - the probability that x occurs if y occurs.

Identities:

Probability of drawing a red queen from a deck of cards given that the card drawn is red:

Clearly, P(\text{red} \cap \text{queen}) = P(\text{red} \mid \text{queen}) \cdot P(\text{queen}).
Since the card is a queen, P(\text{queen}) = 1 and P(\text{red} \mid \text{queen}) \cdot P(\text{queen}) = P(\text{red}) = \frac{1}{2}.

Gambler's Fallacy

When a set of events are independent, people are prone to thinking that the events are dependent of the conjoint probability of each of the other events in the set.

In other words, given events x_1, \ldots, x_n such that \forall 1 \le i \le n, 1 \le j \le n, P(x_i) = P(x_i \mid x_j) (all events are independent), it is a mistake to assume P(x_i) \ne P(x_i \mid x_j).

For example, if we flip a coin 9 times and it comes up heads every time, then it is a fallacy to think that the next flip will have anything but a 50% chance of coming up heads.

The gambler's fallacy is committed whenever, after observing something that happens more often than usual, we predict that it will happen less often in the future in order to "balance out".

Regression Fallacy

If we flip a coin 9 times and it comes up heads every time (this is a pattern that is far from the mean), then in reality, a phenomenon known as regression to the mean says that it is likely that the next set of flips will average out to the mean - that the next set of flips will be 50% heads.

Regression to the mean says that if we flip enough times, eventually it will tend toward the average.

Note that this does not contradict the gambler's fallacy - regression to the mean says that the next set of flips is likely to be average, while the gambler's fallacy says that the next flip is 50% likely to be heads.

A regression fallacy is when we think there is a cause when there is no cause, due to natural variations.

The regression fallacy is committed whenever, given a random event, one assigns a cause where there is only natural variation.

For example, "Jim did exceptionally well at work last year. His performance is merely average this year, so something must have happened.".

This is fallacious because it is likely that in fact this is just natural variation in performance, not caused by any external factors.

When we see a number of extraordinary events happening, we tend to think that they are ordinary. However, they are not; this is just natural variations in the events.

A related concept is the regression effect. Basically, if we pick a number between 1 and 100, and draw a 1 the first time, the next draw will be still be independent, yet the probability of a bigger number is 99%, and the probability of a number closer to the mean is 98% (since 100 is equally far from the mean).

Simpson's Paradox

Suppose hospital A cures 70% of all cancer patients and 90% of all non-cancer patients. Suppose hospital B cures 50% of all cancer patients and 80% of all non-cancer patients.

We might be inclined to believe that hospital A has a better overall cure rate, since the rates for both are higher, but this is not always true.

It is easy to find a counterexample:

Hospital A might have 700/1000 (70%) cancer patients cured, and 9/10 (90%) non-cancer patients cured, giving an overall rate of 709/1010, or 70.2%.

Hospital B might have 5/10 (50%) cancer patients cured, and 800/1000 (80%) non-cancer patients cured, giving an overall rate of 805/1010, of 79.7%.

The problem arose when we tried to add percentages together.

The fallacy is that the total percentage of A cannot be compared to the total percentage of B by comparing the percentages of the individual parts of A and B.

Comparisons that hold within all parts of a set do not necessarily hold for the set as a whole. This is a compositional fallacy.

7/3/14

Biases

A bias is a systematic preference or tendency to favor one outcome over another. Biases can lead to people reasoning in unreliable ways, but many biases exist for very good reasons - they are what allows us to think so effectively.

Heuristics are simplified problem solving techniques used to solve complex problems quickly. They are closely associated with biases.

Heuristics have allowed humans to become extremely effective in practical problem solving. They can sometimes be useful, but can sometimes lead to biases.

Biases are often useful in a variety of situations, but they usually have a small class of problematic cases. The problem is distinguishing whether a bias is helpful, or leads to reliable reasoning.

Another example of baises is seeing shapes in the clouds, or seeing faces where there are none. This may be due to the need for earlier humans to detect predators more effectively and avoid them.

10/3/14

As a general rule, when we add quantities that have ratios, the resulting ratio is between the largest of the ratios and the smallest of the ratios.

For example, if one box is 20% full and another 80% full, then when we combine the boxes together, the result is always between 20% and 80% full.

Types of Biases

Cognitive biases are those biases associated with cognition. They are caused by our psychological characteristics, and even things like our beliefs, expectations, and fears.

Some examples of cognitive biases are:

Perceptual biases are those that affect what we perceive. They are a subset of all cognitive biases.

Most optical illusions work based on low-level or bottom-up perceptual biases. These are biases that are introduced in the low-level processing that the brain does when precessing the raw sensory input.

For example, if we are talking to someone, what we perceive from the lip movements can significantly affect what we hear. This is known as the McGurk effect. It probably exists to help detect errors in speech recognition and improve communication in noisy places. Interestingly, it works even if we are aware of the effect.

Perceptual biases can also be introduced by explicit, conscious reasoning - top-down perceptual biases.

12/3/14

Critical thinking is a matter of learning not to trust yourself too much.

From this overview of biases, we can see that our reasoning is prone to being unreliable at times, however much we try to avoid it. When performing critical thinking, we must take these factors into account to reason more reliably.

Reasoning about others

A stereotype is a set of properties associated with a certain class of objects. Social stereotypes are those sterotypes associated with a certain group of people.

Stereotypes can lead to unreliable reasoning. It is connected to the prototype theory of concepts, where membership of an object in a class is defined by how close it is to the "prototypal" member of that class. For example, a stool would be considered a member of the class of furniture, because it is quite close to a prototypal piece of furniture, a chair.

Stereotyping allows us to look as a stool, compare it with the stereotype, the chair, and efficiently determine whether it is furniture or not.

For example, two groups are given almost identical papers to evaluate, where one group has commonly male names on the papers and the other group has commonly female names on the papers, and the group with male names gives consistently higher scores, revealing that gender biases are much deeper than most people would think. Even though the test subjects believed they were being objective, biases can still be introduced.

14/3/14

Apparently we didn't do much on Wednesday, probably because of the snow. This class was a review of last class' notes.

17/3/14

Communication

Communication has multiple goals, such as to entertain, scare, or deceive, in addition to transmitting or receiving knowledge. Truth is not the only factor considered when deciding what to share or listen to.

Fundemental attribution error is the tendency to explain someone's situation or behaviour based on their personality, character, or disposition while overlooking explanations based on context, accidents, or other effects.

For example, poverty might be explained as failings of character such as laziness, when there are likely numerous other effects causing this situation.

21/3/14

The false polarization effect is the tendency to overestimate the extent to which someone's views resemble the strongest/sterotypical views of this sort, and the difference between one's own views and the views of people disagreeing.

Bandwagon effects are tendencies to prefer views that they think are held by other people - the idea that "if most other people believe it, then it is likely right". This may be caused by believing that everyone else has justification, and possibly because defending a minority view requires effort.

The false consensus effect is the tendency to believe that the absence of disagreement is agreement. This is due to the convention that assertions are considered accepted until challenged. However, in practice there are social costs to dissenting, and there are therefore pressures not to express the dissenting view. In other words, it is the tendency to believe that one's own opinion is the norm.

Society allows us to access information otherwise unavailable, but information might not flow perfectly - it can become corrupted, and there are other aims to communication that can lead to unreliable reasoning. Which social group we associate with will bias the information we have access to.

For example, we might think that Harper is a highly respected prime minister, but this likely reflects our friend group more than the view of all Canadians.

For efficiency reasons, humans interpret stories, arguments, and reports, and identify the "main points" rather than memorizing the whole thing. As a result, every reading of every article is relative to the reader's state of information, preferences, and world view.

When we relay information, we tend to emphasize the information perceived to be important/relevant (sharpening), while deemphasizing the less important/relevant aspects (leveling). Repeated sharpening or levelling over multiple relayings can heavily distort the original information.

People also tend to correct the aspects of reports that they find implausible relative to their own views.

24/3/14

Science

Science is seen as an authority or privileged source of information. It has high standards for empirical evidence and follows very careful methods to most successfully obtain information.

The philosophy of sciecne is a subcategory of philosophy, like metaphysics or epistemology. It focuses on questions such as what should be considered science, how it relates to our learning about world, and how science should be done.

Science is a term applied to two distinct things: a set of social activities (experiment design, running experiments), and the representations (hypotheses, theories, laws, models, etc.) and artifacts (instruments, machines, etc.) that result from this.

We can then define science in terms of these two things. There is the practice of science, which results in the products of science.

The demarcation problem is the problem of determining whether something is or isn't science. This is a useful problem to consider because it can help us understand how some sources of information aare better than others.

For example: astronomy vs. astrology. It is generally agreed that the former is science, while the latter is pseudo-science.

Some common criteria for demarcating science are:

26/3/14

Theory-ladeness is a phenomenon where all observations are always made against some sort of existing theory and assumptions. In other words, all theories in a paradigm are tied to that paradigm.

For example, in psychology the diagnoses of a condition is almost always dependent on the mental model being used.

For example, in electricity, the idea of current is theory-laden because it is tied to our current model of electricity, where electrons flow around.

28/3/14

The Popperian falsifiability criteria states that something is scientific if it can be falsified - if there is a practical way of showing that it is false.

In this model, a theory would be more scientifically believable if it survived strong attempts to falsify it - if it passes tests that appeared to be very likely to make it fail.

However, Quine proposed that there are also intiial conditions and auxilary hypotheses to account for - hypotheses that must be true at the same time as our main hypothesis in order for the conclusion to be true.

Because of this, falsifying evidence might not actually falsify a theory because it is also possible that one of our auxilary hypotheses are false. For example, "If Mary studies for the test, then Mary will do well" has many auxilary hypotheses, such as "Mary writes the test" and "The test was graded fairly".

Even if the conclusion is falsified, "Mary did not do well on the test", we can only say that one of the hypotheses were false, and it still might be true that "Mark studied for the test".

This is covered in more depth in the Philosophy of Science section in the PHIL110A notes.

The difference between science and pseudoscience can also be said to be whether it uses the scientific method:

  1. Observe a phenomenon.
  2. Form hypothesis to explain phenomenon.
  3. Deduce implications of hypothesis.
  4. Observe some more phenomenon to test hypothesis.
  5. Evaluate hypothesis by checking it and its implications against the observations.

Thagard proposed that a discipline is pseudoscience if it is less progressive than alternative theories, and the community does not attempt to develop theories to solve problems, or look at evidence in an unbiased way.

Science can also be defined by its use of peer review and the way it takes advantage of social cognition. It may be that the structure of the communities themselves determine whether a practice is science or not.

Science is simply application of critical thinking to empirical evidence. Instead of focusing on what is and isn't science, we should instead focus on what methods of generating information are reliable.

A single blind study is one where the participants are not given all the information, but the experimentors are, to avoid bias.

A double blind study is one where both the participants and experiments are not given all the information, to avoid bias.

Consistency

Consistency between theories also affects whether a theory is a good one. A theory that fits with existing theories is more likely to be scientific, and vice versa.

Consilience is a related concept - where a theory developed for one domain also explains phenomena in another domain. For example, the Newtonian theory of gravitation explains the motion of planets, but also the tides on Earth.

If we generalize this, we might find that we want science to give a single, unified world view, like how Maxwell unified electricity and magnitism into electromagnetism.

Reliability

We can judge whether some scientific activity is likely reliable by looking at its features and products.

First, it must be driven by evidence. It should use something like the scientific method, heavily scrutinize the resulting theories, and make use of all evidence available in an objective way.

Second, it must produce hypotheses/theories that can actually be evaluated against real evidence. It should be verifiable or falsifiable, having clear implications and fitting well with existing theories.

Creative Commons License This work by Anthony Zhang is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-ShareAlike 4.0 International License. Copyright 2013-2017 Anthony Zhang.